| |
- Individuality
and Generalization
in the Psychology of Personality: A Theoretical Rationale for Personality Assessment and Research Robert R. HoltProfessor of Psychology Emeritus, New York University Part 1 of three partsGo to Part
2Go to Part
3 (Bibliography)Vai alla versione italiana: Parte
1, Parte 2, Bibliografia
Introduction by
PaoloMigone In the past months, some discussion lists of psychiatry,
psychology and psychotherapy have been heated by lively debate on the scientific
status of psychotherapy. Several colleagues were suggesting that a so-called
idiographic approach, rather than a nomothetic one, was more suited for the
psychotherapeutic enterprise. According to the idiographic approach, they say, the
object of study is unique [idios], not amenable to the generalizing
laws [nomos] of the nomothetic approach, which is typical of
natural sciences. In order to contribute to this debate, in the Psychotherapy
section of POL.it here we publish a classic paper on this topic,
written by Robert Holt in 1962, which shows how this problem was faced by an
exponent of an important line of research in psychology. In fact, the topic is
not new, and it is striking that it continues to raise lively debates
without an easy solution; actually this is just what makes it interesting.
This debate was already active in the United States in the '40s around the
issues of personology (the study of personality) and Holt was a first hand
witness. At that time Holt was a pupil of Gordon Allport, the famous
personality theorist and strong believer in the idiographic approach. In contrast
to his teacher, Holt took an opposite position and believed that the
idiographic approach had to be simply abandoned and used only for artistic, non
scientific purposes. His logical arguments are set out in this paper, which
appeared for the first time in the Journal of Personality, 1962, 30, 3:
405-422, and soon became a classic, being republished several times. The
Italian translation appeared in the Bollettino di Psicologia Applicata,1963, 57/58: 3-24. The version published here is not the 1962
version, but a new edition published in 1978 when it appeared the two volumes
by Holt Methods in Clinical Psychology: Assessment, Prediction and Research
(New York: Plenum, 1978); furthermore, the author has added new notes
and a few changes, so that the version published here can be considered a
new, final edition of this paper, reflecting the more recent development
of the author's thinking. Two forewords are published here: the first one
has been written in 1998 purposely for this POL.it edition, and the
second one, with minor changes, appeared in the aforementioned 1978 edition.
We thank the Journal of Personality for the permission to reproduce
this paper in the English version, and the Organizzazioni Speciali (O.S.) of Florence for the Italian edition. I translated both
forewords and the new parts of the article, of which I also improved the
overall translation. This article, here published in both English and Italian
languages, appears as the sixth document of the Psychotherapy
section of POL.it. Finally, few words about Robert Holt. He is already know to
Italian readers because many of his works have been translated. In Italy he
is known mostly for his writings in theoretical research in
psychoanalysis, which occupied a later phase of his professional life, when he
entered the prestigious research group led by David Rapaport. There, with the
scholarly precision which is typical of him, and also under the mentorship of
Rapaport (who was one of the most important theorist in psychoanalysis), he
studied psychoanalytic metapsychology. After Rapaport's death, when he was
viewed by some as his successor as the leader of the group, he came to take amore critical stance towards Freudian metapsychology. Among other
things, he made a lot of work in psychological testing (for instance, he
edited the second edition of the classic Diagnostic Psychological Testing
by D. Rapaport, M. Gill & R. Schafer of 1945-46 [New York: Int.
Univ. Press, 1968]). A collection of his writing, from his pioneering
critical essays to metapsychology of the '60s to his most recent works, was
published in 1989 with the title Freud Reappraised: A Fresh Look at PsychoanalyticTheory (New York: Guilford, 1989). For a cultural biography of
Holt, with a detailed bibliography, see chapter 13 of my book Terapia
psicoanalitica (Milano: Franco Angeli, 1995); a short biographical
and cultural profile (in Italian) of Bob Holt is also on the Internet at
the web site http://www.psychomedia.it/pm/modther/biogr/holt-bio.htm.
Foreword by Robert Holt
to this edition (1998) In a book that made a great impression on me, Gerald Holton (1973)
noted that "there have coexisted in science, in almost every period
since Thales and Pythagoras, sets of two or more antithetical systems or
attitudes, for example, one reductionist and the other holistic", adding: In addition, there has always existed another set of
antitheses or polarities, even though, to be sure, one or the other was at a
given time more prominent -- namely, between the Galilean (or, more
properly, Archimedean) attempt at precision and measurement that purged public, "objective"
science of those qualitative elements that interfere with reaching reasonable"
objective" agreement among fellow investigators, and, on the other hand, the intuitions, glimpses, daydreams, and a priori
commitments that make up half the world of science in the form of a personal, private,
"subjective" activity. Science has always been propelled and
buffeted by such contrary or antithetical forces (Holton G., Thematic
origins of scientific thought: Kepler to Einstein. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1973, p. 375). The objective-subjective dichotomy goes beyond the boundaries of
science itself, however. I feel that my own interest in the holistic and
subjective approach to psychology has two principal roots: my personal
psychoanalysis, and what might be called my aesthetic interests, which go back as far
as I can remember. Some of my most vivid early memories preserve
experiences of wonder and ecstasy occasioned by a dewy spring morning, by the
sight and scent of wild flowers, even by an Art Deco painting in a magazine
advertisement. My first publications were poems (in literary magazines at prep
school and at college). Some years before, the first reflection I can recall
about a possible career was a wavering between being an artist (of what
kind, I don't recall) and an astronomer. The latter became real enough for
a period in my adolescence when I helped form an astronomy club and worked
for months grinding a mirror for a telescope. Then I discovered and was
enthralled by other sciences: chemistry, paleontology, biology, and
finally psychology. My undergraduate teacher and thesis sponsor, Hadley
Cantril, showed me the intellectual excitement of social psychology and helped
me discover the endless fascination of psychological research. Clinical psychology made it possible for me to retain and
integrate most of these interests and values. Along the way I was gratified by
finding teachers and role models who embodied much of the artist as well as
the scientist: Gordon W. Allport, Henry A. Murray, Robert W. White, David
Rapaport, and Gardner Murphy. These men seemed easily able, in their own lives,
to transcend the split between what C.P. Snow called the "two cultures"
of art and the humanities, and of science. I have of course experienced
the conflict of which Snow wrote, and have found myself pulled in opposite
directions by the effort to ride two such differently-minded horses
simultaneously. Insight into the underlying unities has come slowly, though helped by
identification with mentors. A century or more ago, the underlying conflict in outlooks took
the form of a contrast between nomothetic and idiographic approaches to
personality. Not surprisingly, it continues to be rediscovered and revived by
generation after generation of psychologists and kindred workers. Though I wrote
the first draft of the accompanying paper almost 40 years ago, it seems tome still worthy of being reprinted if it can help some contemporary
scholars, clinicians, or researchers avoid a blind alley of methodological confusion.
Foreword by Robert Holt
to the 1978 edition The paper here reprinted with a new subtitle, was written during
the year 1960-61 (and appeared in the Journal of Personality, 1962,30, 3 [September]: 405-422), though I had been brooding about many of
the issues it considers for two decades. In a real sense it was a kind of
starting point for all my work in clinical and personality psychology; thus, I
reprinted it as the first chapter of my book, Methods in Clinical Psychology(Holt, 1978). Appropriately enough, it appeared cheek by jowl in the Journal
of Personality with a paper by AlIport (1962) on the same general
topic. It was to study with him that Hadley Cantril sent me to do my
graduate studies at Harvard, and though Allport fended off my hero-worshipping
efforts to become his close disciple by a kind of pained and embarrassed
withdrawal, he was one of my main teachers. Sitting in his seminar on personality
theory I became increasingly skeptical about his basic approach, and by the
time I had completed my dissertation--with his considerable help--I had on
my drawing board the sketch of an attack on his methodological position.
Fortunately, the pressure of making a living forced me to put off writing it, for
I did not yet have the historical perspective on the issues that only the
teaching of personality theory would help me gain. During the respite o fa delightful year in the congenial setting of the Center for Advanced
Study in the Behavioral Sciences, I was able to take a fresh look at the
problems and write the following pages. In his accompanying paper, Allport restated a vision he followed
with admirable tenacity all his professional life, of a psychology of
personality that should devote itself to understanding how the structure of the
unique person comes about. In his latter years, after becoming acquainted
with general systems theory, he took over some of its terminology and
tried to adopt its outlook (Allport, 1960; 1961, Chapter 23). Here (Allport,1962) he called for a morphogenetic approach to the system that a
personality constitutes, as opposed to the traditional dimensional tack of
analytic reductionism. Yet he failed to see that the systems outlook amounted
to a Kuhnian revolution, a fundamental transformation of formative
principles in terms of which many of psychology's traditional antinomies became
reconciled. It vindicated his faith in the molar and structural approach to
personalities, his stubborn insistence that there could and should be a science of
individuals, but not his ambivalent polemical rejection of atomism. Part of the
beauty and power of the systems approach is that it finds an appropriate
place or both molar and molecular observations and laws, for both analytic
and synoptic methods, as Weiss (1969) argues so cogently with respect to
the life sciences. As a graduate student, I turned away from Allport partly because
his methodology led to so little by way of useful method. Twenty years
later, he still had come up with few techniques by which to carry out his
program of morphogenetic study of individual persons. He persistently favored
matching, despite the fact that research using this method had led nowhere (or
at least, to very little), concluding lamely: 'Although the method gives
us no insight into causal relationships it is, so far as it goes, a good
example of a 100 per cent morphogenic procedure" (1962, p. 416). In the
same paper, he goes on to recommend several more useful procedures which
actually boil down to two: Baldwin's (1942) personal structure analysis, a
simple statistical method of identifying reliably recurring co-occurrences
of content themes in a person's productions; and interviewing in order to
discover important themes, problems, structural foci, stylistic features,
values, or other traits in a person, sometimes followed up by the use of
generalized rating scales like those of Kilpatrick and Cantril (1960). Partly, I believe, Allport's difficulty was his personal lack of
clinical training and experience, a circumstance that kept him always at a
distance from the personalities he wished to study. In his entire career, he
never made an intensive study of a single personality at first hand! The
apparent exception (Allport, 1965) was a study of a collection of Letters
fromJ enny, carried out after its subject's death; Allport had never
met her. Because he could never see the usefulness of dimensions as more
than weak compromises with true individuality, Allport only fitfully
addressed himself to the task of trying to find useful dimensions. One obvious
difficulty in the realm of personality is the abstractness or non
materiality of our subject matter, as compared to that of a biologist. The latter has no
difficulty with using a concept like mitochondrion or chromosome, because the
things in question are visually recognizable, having a recurrent
distinctiveness of form despite their manifestly unique and fluctuating
configurations in the individual cell. What is a corresponding element, individually
variable, that goes to make up the unique personality? To answer, `the trait'
(as Allport generally did) is simply to substitute another generalized
term for "element." By and large, the traditional approach has
been to fall back on the resources of nonscientific language, as Allport
did himself (in collaboration with Odbert, 1936), accepting such a
descriptive adjective as punctual or dominant as the functional equivalent of an
organelle. Yet such terms are inevitably interactive: they are impressions made
on an observer by a person, judgments rather than perceptions, in which
the orientation of the judge demonstrably plays a very large role. Some
times it is more important than what is in the person under scrutiny,
especially when we get into the very extensive areas of personal behavior that
are socially valued either positively or negatively-- the halo problem. Somehow, we need to find a way of taking a fresh look at people,
without the blinders of standard trait vocabulary. I believe that a case can
be made that concepts like self (a person's reflexive experience and
conception of his own personality), wish, fear, value, ability, and temperament
are the analogues of the cell's fine structure. The psychology of
personality, then, should seek for general laws or generalizations about regular
structural relations among these elements, which may hold regardless of the
unique content of such terms when applied to individuals. (It seems much
less fruitful to look for generalizations on the level of these actual
contents--e.g., the targets of people's values, which are given in such large part by
culture, the appropriate level on which to seek regularities in the value
realm.) Likewise, I am doubtful that it will be helpful to proceed just by
making case studies, even though that may be an indispensable ground on
which to begin work. We can pursue general goals even while ostensibly
bending our efforts to the understanding of unique lives. That at least is
the spirit in which I have tried to work, both as a diagnostic tester and
as a researcher. Individuality and Generalization in the Psychology of Personality: A Theoretical Rationale for Personality Assessment and Research(modified and updated edition of the article "Individuality and generalization in the psychology
of personality", originally published in Journal of Personality,
1962, 30, 3: 405-422) Robert R. HoltProfessor of Psychology Emeritus, New York University
One of the hardiest perennial weeds in psychology's
conceptual garden is the notion that there are nomothetic (generalizing)
and idiographic (individualizing) branches, types, or emphases of science.
Many respected and important contributors to psychology-especially to
personology, the psychology of personality-have quoted these terms with
respect and have used them as if they contributed something useful to
methodology (e.g., Allport, 1937a; Beck, 1953; Bellak, 1956; Bertalanffy,
1951; Colby, 1958; Dymond, 1953; Falk, 1956; Hoffman, 1960; Sarbin, 1944;
Stephenson, 1953; the list could be considerably extended). It is the
purpose of this essay to examine the historical origins of this cumbersome
pair of concepts, their logical implications, the reasons psychologists
espouse them, and alternative solutions to the underlying problems. In so
doing, I hope no doubt fondly, but none the less ardently to lay this
Teutonic ghost which haunts and confounds much of modern psychology.
The principal exponent of the nomothetic-idiographic dichotomy in this
country has been Gordon W. Allport (1937a, 1940, 1942, 1946, 1955), a
pioneer in academic personology and a man who has brilliantly clarified
many important issues in the field. On this particular point, I shall try
to show, the artist in him has probably dimmed the vision of the
scientist. The underlying problem with which Allport wrestles is vexing
enough: the unusual nature of personality as a scientific subject matter.
Allport readily concedes that everything in nature is unique, but
maintains that natural sciences are not interested in the unique leaf,
stone, or river. Only personology, the argument continues, takes as its
very subject matter the unique personality as opposed to the generalized
human mind or the behavior of organisms at large. The rest of psychology
takes care of the general laws of behavior and experience and is thus
nomothetic (literally, setting down laws) [Footnote
1]; what is left over is the impressive fact that every
personality is different and must be studied in such ways as respect and
try to capture this uniqueness in short, by an idiographic science
(literally, portraying what is private or peculiar, i.e., individual).
With these two curious words adopted from Windelband, then, Allport
describes what he sees as two complementary branches of psychology, both
of which are necessary for complete coverage.
Footnote 1: This is the
generally accepted meaning. Brunswik (l943), however, used it in a different
sense, which occasionally causes confusion: as pertaining to a science of
exact laws expressible as functions or equations, and opposed to
statistical generalizations. Both are within the scope of the nomothetic, as
understood here. Rickert used a slightly different term, nomological. On the other hand, many distinguished contributors to
personology, from Freud to Murphy (1947), have found no need for such an approach to
the scientific study of individuality, and the sharp voice of Eysenck (1954)has been heard rebutting Beck (1953) and proclaiming that psychology
should be nomothetic throughout. Clearly, the issue is controversial. Historical background: the romantic movement in science [Footnote2] Footnote 2: In
preparing this historical summary, I have relied principally on Roback (1927),
Allport (1937a, 1937h), Boring (1929), Parsons (1937), L. Stein (1924),
Tapper (1925), Friess (1929), Klüver (1929), and the Encyclopedia of
the Social Sciences. I am aware of some oversimplification in speaking
about the Romantic movement in science; a variety of figures and currents
of thought that could be characterized as romantic may be distinguished in the history of nineteenth-century science, some of them only
loosely related to the movement described here. Kant,
writing in the middle and late 1700s and reacting against reductionism, is
one of the intellectual ancestors of this issue (which can, of course, be
traced back to Plato and AristotleÛlike any other problem in psychology;
see Popper, 1957). Though he did not himself fall into the dualistic
belief that mind and matter were so different that different methods had
to be applied to their study, he wrote about these issues on too
sophisticated a level for his followers. Thus, the analytic and
generalizing methods of natural science were fine for the study of matter,
but the mind, according to the post-Kantians, had to be studied also by an
additional method, intuition of the whole. Being impressed with the
concrete uniqueness and individuality of personality, they did not want to
analyze it but to grasp it by a direct empathic act [Footnote 3]. Footnote 3: For
clarification of Kant's role in these matters, I am indebted to my friend Abraham Kaplan.
Yet for the next century, no one developed such an intuitive approach
to personality into anything; meanwhile, physics and chemistry, and even
some branches of biology, grew rapidly and used the developing scientific
methods with great success in the realm of matter. Mechanics developed
early, and Newton's laws of motion were misunderstood as being foundation
stones of mechanism and materialism. As C. Singer (1959) points out,
Newton's laws were quite abstract and did not deal with physical bodies at
all; but in their early great successes they were applied to the motions
of the planets, and thus were thought of as the laws of material masses.
It could hardly have been otherwise, because of the prevailing tenor of
philosophical and scientific thought. The world was simply not ready for
the field-theoretical implications of Newton's theories. Even so great a
physicist as Lord Kelvin found "meager and unsatisfactory" any
physical knowledge that could not be expressed in a mechanical model.
Though the facts of their own disciplines did not require it, then,
natural scientistsÛhelped along by the overgeneralizations of
contemporary philosophersÛadopted a hard-headed, materialistic, and
mechanistic positivism. It was assumed that all reality was orderly,
classifiable, and susceptible of mechanistic explanation; to the extent
that it seemed not to be, the province of science ended. It was expected
that the secrets of life itself would shortly be reduced to physico-chemical
formulas. The resulting clash with religion and humanism seemed an
inevitable consequence of being a good scientist:
What was not realized was that the success of science was due to the faithfulness of its practice, while its destructiveness[of humanistic, cultural values] arose from the error of its
philosophy which saw that practice as though it were the outcome of a world-view
with which it was in fact fundamentally incompatible (C. Singer, 1959, p.420).
This was a classic atmosphere, ripe for the romantic revolt that
started in poetry at the turn of the nineteenth century and swept through
the arts. The humanities are accustomed to see the pendulum swing from
classicism to romanticism and back again; from a time of reason, order,
control, and clarity to one of passion, ambiguity, free expression, and
revolt. To a degree, such movements are felt in the sciences as well,
though usually less clearly. In science, we have a temperamental
difference between the tough-minded and the tender-minded, as James put
it, or in Boring's phrase, the advocates of nothing but against
those of something more; in the nineteenth century, it was
objectivism and positivism versus subjectivism and intuitionism. The
hard-headed positivists had had their way for a long time; near the end of
the century, however, there was something of a romantic revolt in science,
tipping the balance toward the subjectivists. Independently, in two
different parts of Germany, Wilhelm Dilthey in Berlin and the "southwesterners"
Windelband and Rickert proclaimed the primacy of understanding (Verstehen)
in certain kinds of science over quantification of elements, in the
part of the general intellectual current with which we shall be concerned
here.
They elaborated the distinction between two kinds of science: the Naturwissenschaften,
natural sciences, and Geisteswissenschaften, the German
translation of J. S. Mill's "moral sciences." The latter term,
often retranslated as "social sciences," meant actually a good
deal more, for it included philosophy and the humanities as well as
history, jurisprudence, and much else that is often excluded from social
science today. In an attempt to develop separate methodologies for the Naturwissenschaften
and Geisteswissenschaften, Windelband and Rickert took up,
developed, and popularized a distinction between two types of science that
had been proposed by Cournot, the French founder of mathematical economics
[Footnote 4]. Cournot, who was also
something of a philosopher of science, had a sophisticated concept of
chance and examined the role it played in various fields of knowledge in
the process of classifying them. In the exact sciences, precise laws were
possible, he said, but in history, chance played such a large role that
only a probabilistic discipline was possible. As a later philosopher of
history, Meyer, put it: any particular event "depends on chance and
on the free will of which science knows nothing but with which history
dealt" (Quoted by Weber, 1949,p. 115, from Meyer's Zur Theorie
und Methodik der Geschichte, Halle,1900.)
Footnote 4: See the article
on Geisteswissenschaften in the Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences
and Cournot (1851). The reader who is interested in a richly detailed
picture of the issues and their background will do well to read Popper(1957) and Chapters 13 and 17 in Parsons (1937). An excellent briefer
account is given by Klüver (1929), in which references to the principal
relevant works of Windelband and Rickert may be found. It
should be clear by now that we are dealing with not just a pair of
isolated terms but a complex set of methodological concepts and
viewpoints. The nomothetic-idiographic distinction can no more be
understood out of the context of the geisteswissenschaftliche movement
than can any isolated culture trait torn from its cultural embeddedness.
For the sake of convenience, I shall refer to this complex of ideas as the
romantic movement in science. There have been so many major and subtle
shifts in our outlook that it is difficult for us to see the issues with
the eyes of ca. 1900; recall, however, that vitalism was a live
doctrine then, and the ideas of chance and free will [Footnote
5] were closely connected, respectable concepts. Many scholars
conceived of history as having been shaped primarily by the acts of great
men; as we shall see, the theme of the relation between personality and
achievement is a recurrent preoccupation of the romantics. Footnote 5: At the time
I wrote this paper, I shared the prevailing and largely thoughtless
rejection of free will, accepting as self-evident the proposition that it was
opposed to the scientifically necessary assumption of determinism. I have
since mended my ways; see my papers of 1967a and 1972a; and in my book of 1989,see pp. 246-252. Similar arguments may be found in Russell (1929),
Chein (1972), M.B. Smith (1974), Weiss (1969), and Rubinstein (1997, pp. 440ff.).
It is factually true that history, biography, and literary criticism
are primarily interested in increasing our understanding of particular
events, persons, or works, rather than in treating these as incidental to
the discovery of general laws. But men like Windelband and Rickert took
the jump from this proposition to the sweeping declaration that all of the
disciplines concerned with man and his works should not and by their very
nature cannot generalize, but must devote themselves to the understanding
of each particular, and its integration "as a real causal factor into
a real, hence concrete context" (Weber, 1949, p. 135). The
repetition of the word "real" in this passage underscores the
conception that only the concrete was real, hence abstractions could not
be conceived of as causes of particular events. Moreover, abstract
analysis of specific events or persons was thought to be fallacious, since
it destroyed the unique unity that was the essence of any such particular.
This essence was qualitative, not quantitative, and often consisted of
verbal meanings (as opposed to objective facts, the subject matter of
natural science), which could not be measured but only interpreted. By
identifying Cournot's methodological distinction with their own between
the knowledge of Being (Sein), obtained in physical science, and
the consciousness of and relatedness to norms (Sollen) in the
cultural sciences, Windelband and Rickert started the great debate on the
role of values in science [See Chapter 10 of my Methods in Clinical
Psychology (1978), Vol. 2, "The Problem of Values in
Science"].
For psychology, Dilthey was the most important figure in this movement.
He was a philosopher, an admirer of Goethe and Schopenhauer, rebelling
against Christianity and Hegel, though influenced by the Biblical
hermeneutics of Schleiermacher. He wanted to respect the heart's reasons
the head will never know, to understand life in its own terms, not to
explain it. The anti-intellectual element in such a goal is perceptible,
and indeed, he is part of the current in German thought that provided the
philosophical background for Nazism. He wanted, not a reduction of data
either to physical-material or to idealistic terms, but a direct insight
into the vital nature of things as articulated wholes. His approach was
empirical, but in a different sense from the atomistic English tradition,
stressing the importance and primacy of the unbroken whole, the Strukturzusammenhang.
Obviously, he helped prepare the seedbed for Gestalt psychology. He
was optimistic, unlike some of his successors (e.g., Spengler), and very
influential in Germany.
Basic to the development of the social and cultural sciences, he
thought, was the development of a new psychology, which he called verstehende
psychologyÛa descriptive discipline concerned with the systematic
knowledge of the nature of consciousness and of the inner unity of the
individual life, and with the understanding of its development. It did not
analyze or start with elements, but with experienced relationships. The
most important unifying forces in a man were purpose and moral character.
He saw the intimate relation of the person to his social setting and
insisted that individual human character was an outgrowth of institutions,
not vice versa.
These are only fragments from Dilthey's large output of ideas, which
lacked system and order; his work was brought together only after his
death, by friends. Nevertheless, it stimulated many workers in diverse
fields: jurisprudence, economics, sociology, philosophy, genetics,
history, and psychology.
Dilthey's most important psychological follower was Spranger, who is
known chiefly for his book Lebensformen (Spranger, 1922; translated
as Types of Men). He too distinguished sharply between explanatory
and descriptive psychology, favoring the latter, verstehende, type.
Verstehen, he says, is the mental activity "that grasps events
as fraught with meaning in relation to a totality." He was opposed to
the analysis of personality into elements, but wanted to stay on the level
of "intelligible wholes." As a focus for the study of
individuality, he followed Dilthey again in proposing that the person's
values, which determined the direction of his strivings, be considered of
primary interest.
Dilthey had propounded three forms of Weltanschauung which
underlie and pervade the personalities as well as the doctrines of the
philosophers whom he studied. Spranger proposed his famous six ideal types
of values, to which actual individual values more or less correspond: the
theoretical, economic, aesthetic, social, political, and religious. He did
not recognize the possible cultural determination of his choosing just
these six, but traced them back to instincts. Each value type has its own
ethics (e.g., economic: utilitarianism; aesthetic: harmony), and its own
style of life in many other ways. The entire scheme was rather ingeniously
worked out.
This theory followed the new ideas in stressing the unity of
personality, the way in which many details of behavior become
comprehensible when we know such key facts about the total structure as
the principal values toward which a man is oriented. To underline the
contrast between the prevailing atomistic psychology and his own, Spranger
called it Struktur psychology. As a general theory of personality,
it suffers from incompleteness, and its main influence today comes from
its having stimulated the production of a widely used paper and pencil
test, the Allport-Vernon-Lindzey Study of Values, which is still in active
use as a research instrument.
The history of the psychology of Struktur and Verstehen
since Spranger is not yet finished. Its influence is still felt in
personology, and as a school it still has adherents in Germany. Allport
has done the most to bring it to this country; there were a number of
lesser figures, but they have not made significant contributions.
William Stern, a man of some influence in psychology, must be at least
briefly mentioned even though he began in intelligence testing and his
work converged only rather late with the main line of development traced
above. The nomothetic-idiographic distinction played no part in his
writings, though he was influenced by verstehende psychology. He
had been a pioneer and an established figure in child psychology and the
psychology of individual differences, when he became convinced that
conventional psychology was wrongly conceived. As differential
psychologists, he said, we are studying isolated mental functions, the
ranges and correlates of their variations, but overlooking the important
fact that all such functions are embedded in personal lives. As child
psychologists, we talk about the growth of intelligence or the like,
forgetting that only persons grow. Reasoning thus, and basing his
psychology on his personalistic philosophy, he decided that a radical
rebeginning was imperative; psychology had to be rebuilt with the
indivisible, individual person as the focus of every psychological
investigation. Even Gestalt psychology with its emphasis on totalities and
its similar antielementarism was insufficient, for: "Keine Gestalt
ohne Gestalter." Stern went into most of psychology's classical
problems, such as perception, making the point that there are not separate
problems of spatial perception in hearing, vision, touch, etc. there is
only one space, personal space, and it is perceived by whatever
means is appropriate. Most of the facts that had been established in
traditional general psychology were brought in, with this new twist.
Stern's theory of motivation was a complex one, including drives
(directional tendencies), instincts (instrumental dispositions), needs,
urges, will, pheno-motives and geno-motives, etc., in too subtle and
highly elaborated a structure to be recounted here. He did not have a
theory of personality as such; rather, the personalistic viewpoint
pervaded all of his general psychology. There was a specific theory of
character, however, conceived of as the person's total make-up considered
from the standpoint of his acts of will, his conscious, purposive
striving. Though stratified, character is a unified structure and may be
described by a list of traits, but this is only the beginning; much stress
was laid on the particular, concrete structure. Particular traits, said
Stern, no matter how precisely described, have meaning only when you see
what function they play in the structure of the whole personality.
These are the principal psychological figures in the stream of ideas
that produced the distinction between nomothetic and idiographic Wissenschaften
and then applied the latter approach to the problems of psychology.
Perhaps the name of Jaspers, in psychopathology, should be added. He helps
to establish the continuity between the romantic movement at the turn of
the century and the contemporary existentialist-phenomenological movement
in psychiatry. The geisteswissenschaftliche point of view made even
more headway in the social sciences, from which some influence still comes
to bear on psychology. Popper (1957) has applied the term historicism to
one of the main streams in sociology, history, and economics that
developed as part of the romantic reaction against positivist,
natural-scientific methodology. Such potent names as Marx, Engels,
Spencer, Bergson, Mannheim, and Toynbee are among the historicists, and
the movement is by no means dead today, despite the vigor of attacks by
logical positivists which have refuted the underlying logic of this
position. I will not further consider this important group of theorists,
who have been adequately routed (Popper, 1957; cf. also Popper, 1950).
How useful were the new ideas to the group of psychologists discussed
above? What they took from the romantic revolt was its emphasis on the
permission to study as legitimate objects of inquiry, personality, values,
motivation, and the interrelation of such factors with cognition (e.g.,
ideology, perception). Starting with Dilthey's first disciples and going
on through the solid contributions of Spranger and Stern, these men did
not adhere to a strict distinction between idiographic and nomothetic
approaches, and were disinclined to make any substantial change in their
accustomed ways of scientific work. Any follower who wholly gave up
general concepts and stuck closely to intuitive contemplation of
indivisible Gestalten simply dropped out of the picture. The men who are
remembered used the new battle cries to help shift their fields of
activity slightly, and to develop new types of concepts, which as concepts
were on no different level of abstractness from the ones Dilthey and the
southwesterners attacked so vehemently.
Note, for example in the above summaries, the generalizing, abstract
nature of the motivational concepts used by Spranger and Stern: both
retained values and instincts, which were assumed to be found in all
persons.
As soon as they stopped their polemics and got down to work, the men of
this romantic revolt strayed off the intuitive reservation and came up
with conceptual tools methodologically indistinguishable from those of
so-called nomothetic science. In a way, Stern was the most consistent in
the attempt of his General Psychology from a Personalistic Standpoint (1938)
to reshape all of psychology from bottom to top; but on closer
examination, the changes turn out to be largely verbal. It is all very
well to talk about personal space, for example, but no idiographically
personalistic research methods were developed. One could hardly say that
there has been any further development of a personalistic psychology of
perception, except in the sense that Stern has helped focus attention on
new types of generalized variables derived from a study of individual
differences in perceptual behavior (see Klein & Schlesinger, 1949).
Nevertheless, all of this work did represent an important ground swell
in the history of ideas, and it had some useful influence on the
behavioral sciences. It did not make them idiographic, but it directed
their attention to new or neglected problems and novel kinds of variables,
as well as to the issue of structure: the ways the variables are
organized. Like many rebellions, it revolted against a tradition that was
stultifying, only to produce an opposite extreme, which if taken literally
would have been equally useless or more so. Fortunately, scientists only
occasionally take their concepts quite that literally and with such
logical consistency. Especially at a time that old ideas are overthrown,
the important content of the new movement is often emotional. Through the
drama of overstatement, a prevailing but opposite overemphasis may be
overthrown, and in calmer times other men may find a sensible position
from which to move forward [Footnote 6].
Footnote 6: As stated here,
the text seems to imply that the solution is a compromise, whereas I am
now convinced that nothing less than a change of ethos or age, in Ackoff's
(1974) phrase, is involved. See footnote 18, below. Certainly
the psychology and social science that held the stage in Germany during
the 1880s and 1890s were in many ways inadequate as scientific approaches
to important human problems. It was a day when not only value judgments
but even an interest in the psychology of values was banned from
scientific concern. Fechner and Wundt had started with problems it is easy
to dismiss as trivial, minute, or far removed from what the man on the
street thinks of as psychology. Experimental psychology had to start that
way, and it can now look back on an illustrious, slow development of
methods and concepts, which today permit laboratory studies of personality
and some of life's more pressing issues. But a century ago, is it any
wonder that a person who was interested in man the striver, the sufferer,
the spinner of ideologies as Dilthey wasÛthought that the classical
scientific approach itself might be at fault? Surely the world of inner
knowledge, of passions and ideals, had been left out, and the verstehende
movement was a revolt against this one-sidedness. The historical role of differential psychology
In psychology, the romantic movement has been felt particularly in
personology, the psychology of personality. And one reason that its impact
was particularly great there is the fact that personology grew out of
differential psychology, the psychology of individual differences.
The first efforts of the "new psychology" of the 1890s were
devoted to finding empirical generalizations and abstract laws about such
functions as sensation and perception (concepts which themselves were the
heritage of faculty psychology). It was what Boring has called the science
of the average, healthy, adult (and, one might add, male) mind, a subtly
Aristotelian conception that generally relegated the study of women and
children, and of abnormal and exceptional behavior, to a subordinate
status. Even so, there remained embarrassing observations of exceptions to
the general laws even when the subjects were "average, healthy
adults." Accordingly, the field of differential psychology was
invented as a kind of wastebasket to take care of these annoying
anomalies. From the standpoint of the highest type of psychology, which
was concerned with laws in a way not expected of differential psychology,
the unexplained residual variance continued to be considered error and to
be treated as if it were random and unlawful.
The psychologists who were content to work with the miscellany of
leavings from all the high-caste tables in psychology were further
handicapped by the taint of practical application, for they were
principally involved in applying psychology to mundane problems like
educating children, treating the disturbed, and selecting employees. Such
work called for the prediction of behavior, and it quickly became apparent
that the general laws provided by "scientific psychology" left a
great deal unpredicted; it was practically imperative to supplement them
by some kind of lore that dealt with all the other important determinants.
As time went on, differential psychologists made a radical shift in
approach. In the era when individual differences were thought of as error
as
not lawful, really they were catalogued and measured, and a few attempts
were made to parcel out the variance in terms of sex, age, ethnic, group,
and other gross demographic categories. During the past couple of decades,
however, personologists have increasingly begun to recognize that all the
error-terms of standard psychological equations are their own happy
hunting grounds. Individual differences in such hallowed perceptual
phenomena as time-error, size-estimation, and shape-constancy proved to be
not random at all but reliably related to other dimensions of individual
differences in cognitive phenomena and in noncognitive realms, too (see
Gardner, Holzman, Klein, Linton, & Spence, 1959).
The fallacy involved in treating individual differences as if they were
random and unlawful resembles that of the eighteenth-century scientists
who concretized Newton's laws as propositions concerning mechanical
bodies. In both cases, the grasp of certain principles lagged behind what
could have been expected. Objectively viewed, the laws that govern
individual variation in the perception of apparent movement are just as
abstract as the laws that cover the general case, and seem to have a
different methodological status only because of the accident of history
that brought about the discovery of the latter first. And, despite the
implied promise in Klein and Schlesinger's title (1949), the study of such
general principles does not bring the perceiver, the person in Stern's
sense, back into perceptual psychology. It is merely a change in the axis
of generalization, so to speak, not a way of becoming less abstract about
perception.
End of Part 1Go to Part
2Go to Part
3 (Bibliography)Vai alla versione
italiana: Parte 1, Parte 2,
Bibliografia
|